Gabriel Tarde and the End of the Social

-paper prepared for The Social and its Problems, edited by Patrick Joyce, Routledge, London
Mise en ligne le lundi 10 octobre 2005

a) « Le caractère bizarre et grimaçant de la réalité, visiblement déchirée de guerres intestines suivies de boiteuses transactions, suppose la multiplicité des agents du monde. » Gabriel Tarde, Monadologie et sociologie, p. 93 c)« Au fond de on , en cherchant bien nous ne trouverons jamais qu’un certain nombre de ils et de elles qui se sont brouillés et confondus en se multipliant. » Gabriel Tarde, Les lois sociales, p.61

In order to contribute to this volume on the "social and its problems”, I could have talked about what is known as "actor network theory”, or ANT, a deliberate attempt at terminating the use of the word "social” in social theory to replace it with the word "association”. But I have decided to share with the readers the good news that ANT actually has a forefather, namely Gabriel Tarde, and that, far from being marginalised orphans in social theory, our pet theory benefits from a respectable pedigree. As is written in the official history of the discipline, Tarde, at the turn of the former century, was the major figure of sociology in France, professor at the Collège de France, the author of innumerable books, whereas Durkheim was, at the time, a younger, less successful upstart teaching in the province. But a few years later, the situation had been completely reversed and Durkheim became the main representant of a scientific discipline of sociology while Tarde had been evacuated in the prestigious but irrelevant position of mere "precursor” -and not a very good one at that, since he had been for ever branded with the sin of ‘psychologism’ and ‘spiritualism’. Since then, main stream social theory has never tired of ridiculing Tarde’s achievement and I must confess that I myself never enquired further than the dismissive footnotes of the Durkheimians to check what their rejected ‘precursor’ had really written. And yet, I want to argue in this chapter, through a close reading of his recently republished most daring book, Monadologie et sociologie (M&S), that Tarde introduced into social theory the two main arguments which ANT has tried, somewhat vainly, to champion : a) the nature and society divide is irrelevant for understanding the world of human interactions ; b) the micro/macro distinction stifle any attempt at understanding how society is being generated. In other words, I want to make a little thought experiment and imagine what the field of social sciences would have become in the last century, had Tarde’s insights been turned into a science instead of Durkheim’s. Or may be it is that Tarde, a truly daring but also, I have to admit, totally undisciplined mind, needed a rather different century so as to be finally understood. It could be argued that a thinker of networks before their time could not transform his intuitions into data, because the material world he was interested in was not there yet to provide him with any empirical grasp. Things are different now that the technological networks are in place and that many of the argument of Tarde can be turn into sound empirical use. Whatever is the case, what I really want to do is to present to social theorists my not totally respectable grandfather... not for the sake of genealogy building, but because, on a few technical points of horrendous difficulty, Tarde possessed the solution we have been looking in vain for so long. It is thus to a portrait of actor-network as a precursor of Tarde that I want to devote this paper. Just to get a flavour of the character and understand why he appealed so much to Gille Deleuze, here is how Tarde presented his daring research program in M&S :

‘’I would naively say : Hypotheses fingo. What is dangerous in the sciences, are not close-knit conjectures which are logically followed to their ultimate depths and their ultimate risks ; it is those ghosts of ideas floating in the mind. The point of view of universal sociology is one of those ghosts that is haunting the mind of present day thinkers. Let’s see first where it can lead us. Let’s us be outrageous even to the risk of passing for raving mad. In those matters, the fear of ridicule would be the most antiphilosophical sentiment.’’ p.65

Is this not a good grandfather the one who encourages you to think through as daringly as possible because there is nothing worse than half-baked ‘ghost of ideas’ ? Is it not the case that most of the social sciences is made out of those fleeting ghosts, neither theoretical nor concrete, but merely general and abstract ? Instead of establishing sociology on a complete rupture with philosophy, ontology and metaphysics, as Durkheim will be so proud of doing, Tarde goes straight at them and reclaims as his duty to connect social theory with bold assumptions about the furniture of the world itself. The reader begins to understand, I hope, why Tarde had not a chance in 1900 and why I am so thrilled to feel his genes acting in me, since I have never been able to decide whether I was a metaphysician or a sociologist. If I use extended quotes for this chapter, it is so as to provide his ideas with another chance to spread... The strange specificity of human assemblages The shock of reading S&M begins with the very first pages since instead of talking about « the social » as a specific domain of human symbolic order, Tarde begins with a research agenda, everywhere on the rise in the sciences, according to him, and that he calls monadology : « The monads, Leibniz’ daughters, have come a long way since their father » p.32, he states in the first sentence of the book, just after having repeated in the exergue Hypotheses fingo. We are indeed very far from Durkheim. What is a monad ? It is the stuff out of which the universe is built. But it is a strange stuff, since monads are not material entity only since they are possessed by faith and desire -the verb ‘possess’, as we shall see at the end, takes a great importance in Tarde. No spiritualism nor idealism to expect from this affirmation though, since monads are also completely materialist : they are guided by no superior goal, no grand design, no telos. Each of them, much like Richard Dawkins’s genes or Susan Blackmore memes, fights for its own privately envisioned goal. Finally, monads lead to a thoroughly reductionist version of metaphysics since the small always holds the key to the understanding of the big. "The main objection against the theory of monads, is that (...) it puts, or seems to put, as much or even more, complexity at the basis of phenomena that at their summit’’ p.69. But, here again, Tarde offers a very odd type of reductionism since the smallest entities are always richer in difference and complexity than their aggregates or that the superficial appearances that we observe from far away. For a reason we will understand later, the small is always also the most complex : ‘’[the atom] is a milieu that is universal or that aspires to becomes such, a universe in itself, not only a microcosmos, as Leibniz intended, but the cosmos conquered in its entirety and absorbed by a single being’’ p.57 (his underline). Or even more tellingly : ‘’In the bosom of each thing, there reside every other thing real and possible’’ p.58. It is with this bizarre arrangement of apparently contradictory metaphysics that we have to familiarise ourselves if we want to understand why Tarde had so completely ended the social -or refused to begin with it. In the same way as Tarde refuses to take society as a higher, more complex, order than the individual monad, he refuses to take the individual human agent as the real stuff out of which society is made : a brain, a mind, a soul, a body is itself composed of myriad’s of ‘little persons’, or agencies, each of them endowed with faith and desire, and actively promoting one’s total version of the world. Agency plus influence and imitation, is exactly what has been called, albeit with different words, an actor-network. The link of the two ideas is essential to understand his theory : it is because he is a reductionist -even of a strange sort- that he does not respect any border between nature and society, and because he does not stop at the border between physics, biology and sociology that he does not believe in explaining the lower levels by the higher levels. Such is the key difficulty : human societies are not specific in the sense that they would be symbolic, or made of individual, or due to the existence of a macro organisations. They seem specific to us for no other reasons that, first, we see them from the inside and, second, that they are composed of few elements compared to any of the other societies we grasp only from the outside. Let’s get slowly here : to begin with, we have to understand that ‘society’ is a word that can be attributed to any association :

" But this means that every thing is a society and that all things are societies. And it is quite remarkable that science, by a logical sequence of its earlier movements, tend to strangely generalise the notion of society. It speaks of cellular societies, why not of atomic societies ? not to mention societies of stars, solar systems. All of the sciences seem fated to become branches of sociology.’’p.58.

Instead of saying, like Durkheim, that we ‘’should treat social facts as a thing’’, Tarde says that ‘’all things are society’’, and any phenomenon is a social fact. Nothing extraordinary nor imperialistic here : this does not mean, as with Auguste Comte, that sociology has to occupy the throne to rule over the sciences, but simply that every science has to deal with assemblages of many interlocking monads. The expression ‘plant sociology’ has existed long before human sociology ; ‘société stellaire’ or ‘atomique’ is an expression one will find often in Whitehead ; Bergson, the successor of Tarde at the Collège de France, would feel perfectly at ease with this sentence, and so would contemporary specialists in ‘mimetics’ although in a completely different context. Tarde’s idea is simply that if there is something special in human society it is not be determined by any strong opposition with all the other types of aggregates and certainly not by some special sort of arbitrarily imposed symbolic order which will put it apart from « mere matter ». To be a society of monads is a totally general phenomenon, it is the stuff out of which the world is made. There is nothing especially new in the human realm. So where does the specificity of human societies come from ? From two very odd features : if there is one privilege we have when talking about human societies is that we see them from the inside out so to speak. ‘’When one reaches human societies (...) we feel at home, we are the true components of those coherent systems of persons called cities or states, regiments or congregations. We know everything that happens inside’’p.68. Thus we can easily check that for the only aggregate we know well, no emergent superorganism takes over from the mesh of competing monads. This is the most clearly anti-spencerian as well as anti-durkheimian argument and we have to quote it at length to get the point right :

"But, no matter how intimate, how harmonious a social group is, never do we see emerging ex abrupto, in the midst of its astonished associates, a collective self, which would be real and not only metaphoric, a sort of marvellous result, of which the associates would be the mere conditions. To be sure, there is always an associate that represents and personifies the group in its entirety, or else a small number of associates (the ministers in a State) who, each under a particular aspect, individualise in themselves the group in its entirety. But this leader, or those leaders, are always also members of that group, born from their own fathers and mothers and not born collectively from their subjects or their constituency. Why would it be the case that the agreement of unconscious nervous cells would be able to evoke out of nothing the brain of an embryo, while the agreement of conscious human beings never would have had this capacity in any social group ?’’ p. 68

The argument is so radical that any one in her right mind will recoil from it, but don’t forget the motto of Tarde’s epistemology : the fear of ridicule is not a philosophical virtue. The only reason we believe in emergent properties for the brain of an embryo is because we don’t see the aggregates it links together from the inside. But in the case of human societies, we know for sure that there exist no moi collectif since the representant is never a Leviathan, like Hobbes’s ‘mortal god’, but is always, one of us, born from a mother and father an simply able to ‘individualise the group in him or herself’. If there is no macro society in human group, there is none anywhere. Or to put it in an even more counter-intuitive way : the smaller is always the bigger entity there is. To make sense of it, we have to add the other feature that makes human society apart, which appears even queerer at first : those assemblages are not only seen from the inside, they are also made of very few elements, compared to all the other societies. A polyp, a brain, a stone, a gas, a star, are made of much vaster collections of monads than human societies. In a hilarious moment, Tarde compares the biggest human society of his time, China, with any one of the others. What is a society made of only 300 millions of elements (the size of China at the time) ? ‘’An organism that would contain such a limited number of basic anatomic components would be inevitably located in the lowest degrees of vegetality and animality’’ p.64 (all underlines in quotes are his) ! Any brain is made of more than 300 million aggregates, any speck of dust, any microliter of gas. For most of the societies we consider we have only statistical information averaging out billions of interactions, so we tend to find obvious that for them there is a huge gap between the atomic element and the macroscopic phenomenon. But not for human societies which are made of so few entities : for those, to which we pertain, we know for sure that every single macro factor is made out of determined pathways for which there exist thoroughly empirical traces. No one, in human society can come and claim that, in order to go from one interaction to the next, you have to shift scale and go through a Society or any such Big Animal. Since for the only case we know well, human societies, the small holds the big, it must be the same, Tarde argues, for all the others, except we don’t have the slightest idea on how to reach the monad levels of stones, gas and particles without changing scales. We embrace them only statistically. The macro is nothing but a slight extension of the micro We are so used in the social sciences to speak of levels of complexities, of higher order, of emergent properties, of macrostructure, of culture, societies, classes, nation states, that no matter how many times we hear the argument, we immediately forget it and starts ranking local interactions from the smallest to the biggest as if we could not think without stuffing Russian dolls one neatly into the next. But Tarde is heterarchic through and through. The big, the whole, the great, is not superior to the monads, it is only a simpler, more standardised, version of one of the monad’s goal which has succeeded in making part of its view shared by the others. ‘’Those beautiful coordinations (such as the Civil Codexx) must have been conceived before being put to execution ; they must have begun to exist only as a few ideas hidden in a few cerebral cells before covering an immense territory‘’, he writes in Les Lois sociales (a slightly more disciplined and better composed book published in 1898) p. 116. Tarde is so completely reductionist than even the standardisation -so typical of macroscopic effect- is always brought back to the influence of one element from below -but ‘below’ is of course not the right metaphor. Here again we should go slowly. The first difficulty is to grasp how the big manages not to emerge out of the small but to foreground some of its features. Tarde’s answer appears pretty strange at first :

‘’If we look at the [human] social world, the only one we know from the inside, we see the agents, the humans, much more differentiated, much more individually characterised, much richer in continuous variations, than the governmental apparatus, the system of laws and beliefs, even the dictionaries and the grammars which are maintained through their activities. An historical fact is simpler and clearer that any mental state of any of the actors [participating in it]’’ p.69

As in Stendhal’s novel, The Charterhouse of Parma, Fabrice in Waterloo fills a more complex world than the whole history of the battle that Napoleon has waged -and lost, as any Eurostar commuter like me knows too well... Tarde can be said to have invented microhistory many decades before its discoverers, in the same way as he has invented ANT long before we had any inkling of what a network looked like when he wrote in Les lois sociales (from now on LS) this stunning research program :

‘’In general, there is more logic in a sentence than in a talk, in a talk than in a sequence or group of talks ; there is more logic in a special ritual than in a whole credo ; in an article of law than in a whole code of laws, in a specific scientific theory than in the whole body of a science ; there is more logic in each piece of work executed by an artisan than in the totality of his behaviour.’’ p. 115 LS

He goes so far, in his reductionism -or reverse reductionism since the small is always more complex- that in S&M he uses the same argument on language, the holy place of structuralist explanations, the only indisputable case where the difference between langue and parole should be obvious -but not for him. ‘’People who speak, all with different accents, intonations, pitches, voices, gestures : here is the social element, the true chaos of discordant heterogeineities. But on the long run, from this confusing Babel, a few general habits will be outlined which can be formulated in grammatical laws.’’ p.74 (if not otherwise mentioned all quotes are from M&S). Against any argument in terms of structure beyond or beneath speech acts, Tarde imagines a kind of sociolinguistics, of pragmatics absolutely opposite, in which the structure is only one of the simplified, routinized, repetitive element of one of the locutors who has managed to include his or her local tradition into the general idiom. And there is nothing wrong with this standardisation and extension, since it will immediately allows the monads to differ again, as he immediately adds continuing the sentence above :

"In turn, those [grammatical laws] since they allow many more locutors to speak together, will help them to find a specific turn of phrase : yet another kind of discordances. And those laws will succeed all the more so in diversifying the minds that they will have been better fixed and more uniform.’’ p.74

Macro features are so provisional and have so little ability to rule over the occurrences that they only manage to serve as an occasion for more differences to be generated ! Instead of a structure of language acting through our speech acts, the more structural elements float around in the shape of grammars, dictionary, exemplars, the more they will allow speech acts to differ from one another ! Nowhere has the branch of pragmatics dared moving so far as to say that the structure of language is one speech act among billions of others, a coordination tool that pushes even further the proliferation of differing locutions. The treatment reserved for language, gives an idea of what Tarde is going to do for the social. Instead of moving from, let’s say, Goffman to Parsons, when going from face to face interactions to ‘bigger’ social structure, Tarde keeps the same method for all the levels -there are no levels anyway. Another long quote is necessary here, so odd is the argument at first. To get it, the reader should remember that the big is never more than the simplification of one element of the small :

‘’’Let’s insist on this crucial truth : we are led to it when we remark that, in each of those vast regular mechanisms -the social, the vital, the stellar, the molecular- all the internal revolts that succeed in breaking them are provoked by an analogous condition : their components, soldiers of those various regiments, provisional incarnations of their laws, pertain to them by one side only, but through the other sides, they escape from the world they constitute. This world would not exist without them ; but they would subsist without it. The attributes each element owes to its incorporation in its regiment do not form its entire nature ; it has other leanings, other instincts coming from previous enrolments ; and some which are coming from its own store, from its own proper substance, to fight against the collective power, of which it is a part, but which is only an artificial being, made only of sides and facades of beings.’’p. 80

Extraordinary picture of a social order constantly threatened by immediate decomposition because no component is fully part of it. Every monad overspills the artificial being of any ‘superior’ order, having lend for allowing its existence only a tiny part, a facade of itself ! You can enrol some sides of the monads, but you can never dominate them. Revolt, resistance, break down, conspiracy, alternative is everywhere. Doesn’t have one the impression of reading Deleuze and Guattari Mille Plateaux ? The social is not the whole, but a part, and a fragile one at that ! Understandably, no position can be further from the professional reflex of the social sciences. As Tarde explains with some passion in Les lois sociales : ‘’It is always the same mistake that is put forward : to believe that in order to see the regular, orderly, logical pattern of social facts, you have to extract yourself from their details, basically irregular, and to go upward until you embrace vast landscapes panoramically ; that the principal source of any social co-ordination resides in a few very general facts out of which it falls by degree until it reaches the particulars, but in a weakened form ; to believe in short that while man agitates himself, a law of evolution leads him. I believe exactly the opposite.’’ p. 114 LS

To be a good sociologist one should refuse to go up, to take a larger view, to compile huge vistas ! Look down, you sociologists. Be even more blind, even more narrow, even more down to earth, even more myopic. Am I not right in invoking him as my grand father ? Is he not asking us to join what I have called ‘oligopticon’ instead of panoptica ? Is he not advocating what I have called the ‘flat society’ argument ? The ‘big picture’, the one that is provided by this typical gesture of sociologists drawing with their hands in the air a shape no bigger than a pumpkin, is always simpler and more localised than the myriad of monads it expresses only in part : it could not be without them, but without it, they would still be something. Far from being the milieu in which human grow and live, the social is only a tiny set of narrow standardised connections which occupies only some of the monads some of the times, on the condition that their metrology be strictly enforced and upkept before being inevitable broken up by the inner resistance of the pullutation of infinitesimal actants. As soon as you leave those tiny networks, you are no longer in the social, but down in a confusing ‘plasma’ composed of myriad of monads, a chaos, a brew, that social scientists will do everything to avoid staring in the eyes. There was no way, it should be clear by now, that Durkheim and Tarde could reconcile their view of the social even though they agree to criticise Spencer. They both believe that his biological metaphors are useless to understand human societies, but for totally different reasons. Durkheim fights Spencers because the sui generis human society is irreducible to biological organisms. Tarde fights Spencer, because there exist no organism anyway : since all organisms are societies, human societies cannot be an organism and certainly not a superorganism. This common rejection does not mean that our two forefathers agree, because of an argument that Durkheimians, to these days, have never forgiven Tarde for making : they have simply taken the explanandum for the explanans. Tarde expresses his surprise at Durheim’s uses of the word sociology with great politeness but a devastating irony when he writes in LS :

‘’[My conception], in brief, is almost the reverse of that of Mr Durkheim. Instead of explaining everything by the so called imposition of a law of evolution which would constrain larger phenomena to reproduce, to repeat themselves in some certain identical order, instead of explain the small by the large, the detail by the big, I explain the overall similarities by the accumulation of elementary actions, the large by the small, the big by the detail’’ p.63 LS

It is not only the case that Durkheim has taken society as the cause instead of seeing that it is never more than a highly provisional consequence used as a mere occasion for monads to differentiate yet again, he also has made, according to Tarde, the more damning mistake of distinguishing the social laws from the agents acted by those laws. ‘’We have just seen that the evolution of sociology has led it, here as elsewhere, to descend from the fanciful heights of vague and grandiose causes to the infinitesimal actions which are both real and precise.’’ p. 118 LS. As we saw in the quote a few pages back, Tarde cannot believe that ‘while man agitates himself a law of evolution leads him’. There is no law in social theory that could differ from the monads themselves. It is this distinction between a law and what is subject to the law, no matter how obvious it is for the rest of the social sciences, that Tarde has dismantled with his monadology. This complete shift in the epistemology is the last, but also the most arduous, point I want to tackle in this chapter. But before getting his argument right, we have to understand why he too has made the study of science central to his argument in social theory. Science studies as the test bed of social theory When Tarde wishes to present the best case of what he has in mind when analysing human societies, it is always history of science that comes forward. He puts science studies dead in the centre of social theory, a good 80 years before it was invented ! Is the reader now convinced that he is our ancestor and that I am not making up this genealogy simply out of fear of embracing an orphan theory ? For all the other aspects of human societies, the paths that leads a monad to its spread (we would say the actor and its network) may be lost or erased through custom and habits. There is one exception however, which makes it the most telling example for social theory, and that is the way scientific practice goes from one tiny brain in an isolated laboratory all the way to become the race’s common sense. The tracability of science is complete :

‘’As to the scientific monument, probably the most grandiose of all the human monuments, there is no possible doubt. It has been built in the full light of history and we can follow its development almost from its first inception until today. (...) Everything in it finds its origin in individual action, not only the raw material, but also the overall views, the detailed floor plans as well as the master plans ; every thing, even what is now spread in all the cultivated brains and taught in primary schools, has begun in the secret of a solitary brain.’’ p.125 LS In the same way that no one can claim that society is bigger than the monads for the human society we see from the inside, no one can claim for history of science that there exist a Zeitgeist somewhere, or a culture that could explain (away) why any innovation has spread from one place to the next. We might not be able to document all the moves making the human society coherent through influence, imitation, contamination and routinisation, but we can document it for the unique case of history of science since we benefits from the high quality tools of what we would call nowadays scientometrics.

‘’When a young farmer, facing the sun set, does not know if he should believe his school master asserting that the fall of the day is due to the movement of the earth and not of the sun, or if he should accept as witness his senses that tell him the opposite, in this case, there is one imitative ray, which, through his school master, ties him to Galileo. No matter what, it is enough for his hesitation, his internal strive, to find its origin in the social.’’ p.87-88. LS

We should not be put off by the notion of an ‘imitative ray’. Tarde’s vocabulary is a bit odd, but any reader of mimetics can replace imitative ray by any other more modern metaphor about mutation, kinship selection, reproductive strategy and the like. We may also use the notion of an actor-network to account for the tie between Galileo’s discovery and the farm boy’s hesitation. Nor should we be worried that we have traded a sociological theory for a psychological version, as if Tarde was appealing to individual scientists as innovators to make his point. Although this is what Durkheimians have tried to make him say, no sociology was ever further from psychology than Tarde’s. How can one make the author of this stunning sentence the ancestor of methodological individualism ? ‘’In any one, if we look carefully, we will find nothing but a certain number of he and she that have blurred and confounded themselves through their multiplications’’ p. 61 LS. Exactly as in ANT, whenever you want to understand a network, go look for the actors, but when you want to understand an actor go look through the net the work it has traced. In both cases, the point is to avoid the passage through the vague notion of society. This is why the word ‘scientific genius’ takes under his pen a very strange meaning : we are suddenly faced with a complete redistribution of agencies into a myriad not only of other scientists, but also of brain states !

‘’What does it mean for us to say that any psychic activity is linked to bodily apparatus ? Only that in a society, no one may act socially, may reveal itself in any specific way without the collaboration of a great many other individuals, most of the time ignored. The obscure workers who, by the accumulation of tiny facts, have prepared the apparition of a great scientific theory by a Newton, a Cuvier, a Darwin, are making up in some sense the organisms of which those geniuses are the souls ; and their work is nothing but the cerebral vibrations of which this theory is the consciousness. Consciousness here means cerebral glory, in some way, of the most influential and the most powerful part of the brain. Left to itself, a monad can do nothing.’’ p. 66

And this is the man who has been charged with the sin of psychologism, individualism and, even worse, spiritualism ! The one who dare reducing Newton’s mechanisms to the ‘gloire cérébrale’ of some brain states ! Even Richard Dawkins, a militant defender of Allan Sokal’s epistemology, has not dared reducing his innovations to the mutations of some parts of his brains fighting for supremacy :

‘’This is why any social production having some marked characteristics, be it an industrial good, a verse, a formula, a political idea, which has appeared one day somewhere in the corner of a brain, dreams like Alexander of conquering the world, tries to multiply itself by thousands and millions of copies in every place where there exist human beings and will never stop except if it is kept in check by some rival production as ambitious as itself.’’p. 96

« To have or not to have, that is the question... » It is at this point that Tarde’s epistemology begins really to pay off. As is clear from the last quote, the agencies to deal with, the ones we really have to consider if we wish to explain something are neither human agents nor social structures, but the monads themselves in their efforts to constitute unstable aggregates, what we would call actants or world-building entelechies. Science is not what allows us to study the monads from the outside, as if we were finding the laws of their behaviour, but one of the ways in which they spread and make sense of their world-building activity. Contrary to Leibniz’s monads, they are not connected by any preestablished harmony, and of course for Tarde, there is no God to hold together or pacify his specific sort of metaphysical Darwinism ‘(Leibniz) had to invent preestablished harmony, and for the same reason, materialists have to invoke, as complement of their erratic and blinds atoms, universal laws or the unique formula to which all those laws could be reduced, a sort of mystical commandment to whom all beings would obey and which would emanate from no being whatsoever, sort of ineffable and unintelligible verb which, without having ever been uttered by anyone, would nonetheless be listened to always and everywhere.’’ p. 56

In this extraordinary sentence, Tarde sends both materialists and spiritualists to the drawing board, since they both make the distinction between the actions of the agent and the laws that act on those agents. To speak of laws of nature that would preside over the activity of blind atoms, is even more spiritualist than to endow those atoms with some will and purposes, since it implies that those laws are ‘listening to’ and ‘obey to’ some voice over which has never been ‘uttered by any one’. Materialists believe in ‘mystical commandment’ because their epistemology divorces science from what actants themselves do when they try to make sense of their own aggregations. In a way, a good thirty years before Whitehead, Tarde tries to find a solution to the ‘bifurcation of nature’. Instead of having two vocabularies, one for the agent and one for the causes that make the agents act, one can do with only one, on the condition of allowing the agent to concentrate the whole under some sort of point of view or folding : as I have already quoted, a monad is ‘’a universe in itself, not only a microcosmos, as Leibiniz intended, but the cosmos conquered in its entirety and absorbed by a single being’’ p.57. The sciences -or more exactly the collective theories acting of their own by propagation from brain states to brain states- are also launching themselves to this conquest, but in so doing they don’t write down the laws of nature, they add more differences to it. ‘’In the bosom of each thing, there reside every other thing real and possible’’ p.58 We may now be better equipped to grasp this sentence of Monadologie et sociologie which was going to have so much influence on Deleuze :

‘’To exist is to differ ; difference, in one sense, is the substantial side of things, what they have most in common and what makes them most different. One has to start from this difference and to abstain from trying to explain it, especially by starting with identity, as so many persons wrongly do. Because identity is a minimum and, hence, a type of difference, and a very rare type at that, in the same way as rest is a type of movement and the circle a type of ellipse. To begin with some primordial identity implies at the origin a prodigiously unlikely singularity, or else the obscure mystery of one simple being then dividing for no special reason.’’ p. 73

But what is going to be the bridge allowing one to go from one difference to the next ? Identity is ruled out. What then ? Possession ! In one of the most important sentence of his work, Tarde remarks almost in passing :

‘’So far, all of philosophy has been founded on the verb To be, whose definition seemed to have been the Rosetta’s stone to be discovered. One may say that, if only philosophy had been founded on the verb To have, many sterile discussions, many slowdown of the mind, would have been avoided. From this principle ‘I am’, it is impossible to deduce any other existence than mine, in spite of all the subtleties of the world. But affirm first this postulate : ‘I have’ as the basic fact, and then the had as well as the having are given at the same time as inseparable’’p. 86

Here goes Hamlet, as well as Descartes with his cogito, Heidegger with his Being qua Being, together with thousand of homelies about the superiority of what ‘we are’ above what ‘we have’. Quite the opposite, Tarde instructs us. Nothing is more sterile than identity philosophy -not to mention identity politics- but possession philosophy -and may be possession politics ?- create solidarity and attachments that cannot be matched. ‘’For thousands of years, people have catalogued the many ways of beings, the many kinds of beings, and no one ever had the idea of cataloguing the various kinds, the various degrees of possession. Yet, possession is the universal fact, and there is no better term than that of ‘acquisition’ to express the formation and the growth of any being’’ p. 89. If essence is the way to define an entity within the ‘To be’ philosophy, for the ‘To have’ philosophy an entity is defined by its properties and also by its avidity... No way to escape from Tarde’s logic : take any monad, if you look at what are its properties and its proprietors, you will be led to define the whole cosmos, which would be impossible if you had only tried to define the essence of an isolated identity. This rejection of the philosophy of identity has one final consequence, which is of course crucial for us ANT sociologists : the status of non-humans, for which we have been so often criticised. The crossing of the boundary between humans and non humans has raised many problems for our readers and is often taken as the touchstone on which our social theory should stand or fall. But Tarde offers, a hundred years in advance, a much sturdier solution to this problem, when he shifts attention from essences to properties. ‘’The whole outside universe is composed of souls different from mine, but, in effect, similar to mine’’ p.44. This is not, in spite of the word ‘soul’ a spiritualist argument, but only a way of ending an hypocrisy that claims to say what non-humans are -their identity- and abstaining meticulously from saying what they want -their avidity, possession or properties. After Descartes, here goes Kant and his thing in itself.

‘’Accepting to say that we don’t know the being in itself of a stone, of a plant, and, at the same time to continue saying that they are, is logically inconsistent ; the idea that we form of those entities, it is easy to show it, has for content our mental states, and since, if we empty those mental states, there is nothing left, either we say nothing more than this content when we affirm the existence of that unknowable substantial X, or we are in fact forced to confess that in pretending to say something else, we are saying nothing at all. But if the entity in itself is similar, in effect, to our own being, it can be affirmed since it is no longer unknowable’’p44 .

The logical impossibility that has been so vehemently reproached to ANT scholars -how can you impute will and belief to scallops, microbes, door closers, rocks, cars and instruments when it is always you the humans that does the talking- finds in Tarde a radical but healthy solution : if you don’t want to share avidity and belief with the things you have, then also stop to say what they are. The accusation is upturned and the burden of proof shifted to the accusators. Abstain from the ridiculous solution to say that things exist in themselves but that you cannot know them. Either you talk or you remain silent. But you cannot possibly speak and say that the things you speak about are not in some ways similar to you : they express through you a sort of difference that has you, the speaker, as one of their proprietors. What looks like an impossibility with the philosophy of identity, offers no difficulty with the philosophy of ‘alteration’. Possession is another way of talking about translation. After this too brief presentation of some of Tarde’s arguments in the metaphysics of social theory, we may now understand why so much of ANT appears difficult, and why Tarde’s tradition has remained so far without real descendance : sociologists don’t want to be had.

Blackmore Susan (1999), The Meme Machine, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Callon Michel et Bruno Latour (1981), "Unscrewing the Big Leviathans How Do Actors Macrostructure Reality”, in Knorr, Karin et Aron Cicourel (Knorr, Karin et Aron Cicourel), Advances in Social Theory and Methodology. Toward an Integration of Micro and Macro Sociologies, London, Routledge, p. 277-303.

Deleuze Gilles (1968), Différence et répétition, Paris, PUF.

Deleuze Gille (1988), Le Pli. Leibniz et le Baroque, Paris, Minuit.

Deleuze Gille (1993), The Fold. Leibnitz and the Baroque (translated by Tom Conley), Athlone Press.

Didier Emmanuel (2001), De l’échantillon à la population. Thèse de doctorat., Paris Ecole des mines, Thèse de doctorat.

Hilbert Richard A. (1990), "Ethnomethodology and the Micro-Macro Order”, American Sociological Review, vol. 55, p. 794-808.

Latour Bruno (1988), Irreductions part II of The Pasteurization of France, Cambridge Mass., Harvard University Press.

Latour Bruno (1988), "A Relativist Account of Einstein’s Relativity”, Social Studies of Science, vol. 18, p. 3-44.

Latour Bruno et Emilie Hermant (1998), Paris ville invisible, Paris, La Découverte-Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond.

Law John et John Hassard, (Law John et John Hassard) (1999), Actor Network and After, Oxford, Blackwell.

Milet Jean (1970), Gabriel Tarde et la philosophie de l’histoire, Paris, Vrin.

Mucchielli Laurent (1998), La Découverte du social. Naissance de la sociologie en France, Paris, La Découverte.

Mucchielli Laurent (2000), "Tardomania ? Réflexions sur les usages contemporains de Tarde”, Revue d’histoire des sciences humaines, vol. (3), p. 161-184.

Rogers Richard et Noortje Marres (1999), "Landscapping Climate Change : Mapping Science & technology Debates on the World Wibe Web”, Public Understanding of Science, vol. , p.

Tarde Gabriel (1902), Psychologie économique, Paris, Félix Alcan.

Tarde Gabriel (1969), On Communication and Social Influence. Selected Papers. Edited by Terry N. Clark, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.

Tarde Gabriel (1999 réédition), Les lois sociales, Paris, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.

Tarde Gabriel (1999réédition), Monadologie et sociologie, Paris, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.

Whitehead Alfred North (1920), Concept of Nature, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Whitehead Alfred North (1929 1978), Process and Reality. An Essay in Cosmology, New York, Free Press.


Posted by 상겔스 상겔스

오늘날 타르드의 논문, 저작은 대부분 전자 텍스트로 공개되어 있다. 예를 들어 ÉNAP (École Nationale d'Adoministration Pénitentiaire)에 있는 가브리엘 타르드 도서관(Bibliographie de Gabriel Tarde)에는 타르드가 쓴 잡지논문이나 저작의 초판 등이 다수 공개되어 있다. 목록을 볼려면 여기를 누를 것. 또한 퀘벡대학교의 「사회과학의 고전」(Les crassiques des sciences sociales)의 가브리엘 타르드(Les classiques des sciences sociales: Gagriel Tarde (1843-1904)) 항목에는 타르드가 살아 있을 때 공개된 적이 없는 뒤르켐의 『자살론』에 대한 비판도 포함하여, 거의 모든 타르드의 저작을 입력한 PDF 파일이나 워드프로세서 형태가 공개되어 있다. 그리고 프랑스 국립도서관 사이트인 갈리카(Gallica)에는 타르드를 비롯하여 19세기의 많은 책자나 잡지가 공개되어 있다. "Recherche"로 검색할 수 있고 관람할 수 있을 뿐만 아니라 "Téléchanger"를 선택하면 PDF 파일 형식을 다운로드받을 수 있다.

저작 목록

  • Tarde, Gabriel 1879 Contes et poèmes, Calmann-Lévy. 
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1886 La Criminalité comparée, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1890 La Philosophie pénale,Lyon-Paris: A.Storck et Maloine.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1890 Les Lois de l'imitation: Étude sociologique, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1892 Études pénales et sociales,Lyon-Paris: Storck et Masson.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1893 Les Transformations du droit: Étude sociologique, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1895 La Logique sociale, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1895 Essais et mélanges sociologiques, Storck et Maloine.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1896 Fragment d'histoire future, Paris: V. Giard et E. brière.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1897 L'Opposition universelle: Essai d'une théorie des contraires,Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1898 Études de psychologie sociale, Paris: Giard et E. Brière.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1898 Les Lois sociales, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1899 Les Transformations du pouvoir, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1901 L'Opinion et la foule, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1902 Psychologie économique tome 1, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1902 Psychologie économique tome 2, Paris: Félix Alcan.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 2008 La Morale sexuelle, Paris: Éditions Payot & Rivages [College de Franceでの1901-1902년의 강의록. 1907년에 Archives d'anthropologie criminelle에 수록된 것을 재수록함]

타르드 저작집(Éric Alliez 감수)

・Première série
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Monadologie et sociologie, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-1, Paris: Institut Synthélabo.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1999 La Logique sociale, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-2, Paris: Institut Synthélabo.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1999 L'Oppositon universelle, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-3, Paris: Institut Synthélabo.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Les Lois sociales, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-4, Paris: Institut Synthélabo.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 近刊予定 Essais et mélanges (vol.5)
・Hors série
  • Tarde Gabriel 2000 « Maine de Biran et l'évolutionisme en psychologie, » Paris: Institut Sanofi-Synthélabo.
・Deuxieme série
  • Tarde, Gabriel 2001 Les Lois de l'imitation, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-1, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 2003 Les Transformations du pouvoir, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-2, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 近刊予定 Psychologie économique, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-3, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 200210 Philosophie de l'histoire et sciance sociale: La philosphie de Cournot, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-4, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  • Tarde, Gabriel 200409 La Criminalité comparée, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-5, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.

타르드 논문・서평 등

  1. Tarde, Gabriel 1880 "La croyance et le désir: La posibilité de leur measure," RPFE 10: 150-180, 264-283.
  2. Tarde, Gabriel 1881 "Plaquette sur «La Roque de Gajac au XVe siècle»." [Milet 1970: 20]
  3. Tarde, Gabriel 1881 "La psychologie en économie politique," RPFE 12: 232-250, 401-418.
  4. Tarde, Gabriel 1882 "Les traits communs de la nature et de l'histoire," RPFE 14: 270-291.
  5. Tarde, Gabriel 1883 "La statistique criminelle du dernier demi-siècle," RPFE 15: 49-82.
  6. Tarde, Gabriel 1883 "Revue générale: Quelques criminalistes italiens de la nouvelle école," RPFE 15: 658-669.
  7. Tarde, Gabriel 1883 "L'archéologie et la statistique," RPFE16: 363-384, 492-511.
  8. Tarde, Gabriel 1884 "Darwinisme naturel et darwinisme social," RPFE 17: 607-637.
  9. Tarde, Gabriel 1884 "Revue générale: Études sur le socialisme contemporain," RPFE 18: 173-192.
  10. Tarde, Gabriel 188411 "Qu'est-ce qu'une société? ," RPFE 18: 489-510.
  11. Tarde, Gabriel 188506 "Le type criminel," RPFE 19: 593-627.
  12. Tarde, Gabriel 1886 "Problèmes de criminalité," RPFE 21: 1-25, 122-143.
  13. Tarde, Gabriel 1886 "Analyses: Les criminalités espagnoles et siciliennes," RPFE 21: 662-670.
  14. Tarde, Gabriel 1886 "L'avenir de la moralité," RPFE 22: 400-407.
  15. Tarde, Gabriel 1887 "Positivisme et penalité," AAC 2: 32-51.
  16. Tarde, Gabriel 1887 "Statistique criminelle pour 1885," AAC 2: 407-413.
  17. Tarde, Gabriel 1887 "Revue générale: La psychologie criminelle," RPFE 24: 625-644.
  18. Tarde, Gabriel 1888 "La dialectique sociale," RPFE 26: 20-41, 148-165.
  19. Tarde, Gabriel 1888 "Revue générale: La crise de la morale & la crise du droit pénal," RPFE 26: 379-396.
  20. Tarde, Gabriel 1888 "Les deux sens de la valeur," Revue d'économie politique 2: 526-540,561-576.
  21. Tarde, Gabriel 1888 "Les actes du congrès de Rome," AAC 3: 66-80.
  22. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "Catégories logiques et institutions sociales," RPFE 28: 113-136, 292-309.
  23. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "Le crime et l'épilepsie," RPFE 28: 449-469.
  24. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "L'affaire Chambige," AAC 4: 92-108.
  25. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "Revue bibliothèque: Emmanuele Carnevale. La questione della pena di morte, (Turin, Bocca, 1888)," AAC 4: 213-217.
  26. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "Rapport sur la XIe question: Sur la responsabilité morale," AAC 4: 356-369.
  27. Tarde, Gabriel 1889 "L'atavisme moral," AAC 4: 237-265.
  28. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 "La misère et la criminalité," RPFE 29: 505-518.
  29. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 "Analyses: Delbœuf, Magnétiseurs et médicins,Alcan, 1890, in-8, 115pages.," RPFE 30: 93-95.
  30. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 "Le délit politique," RPFE 30: 337-360.
  31. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 "La France criminelle, par II. Joly (Cerf, 1889)," AAC 5: 195-205.
  32. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 "L'amour morbide," AAC 5: 585-595.
  33. Tarde, Gabriel 1890 Les maladies de l'imitation, Revue Scientifique.
  34. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 "L'Art et la Logique," RPFE. 31: 123-147, 288-312.
  35. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 "Revue général: Études criminelles et peéales," RPFE 32: 483-517.
  36. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 "L'affaire Wladimiroff," AAC 6: 206-213.
  37. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 "À propos de deux beaux crimes," AAC 6: 453-465.
  38. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 "L'archéologie criminelle en Périgord," AAC 6: 569-584, .
  39. Tarde, Gabriel 1891 L'idee de culpabilité, Revue des Deux Mondes.
  40. Tarde, Gabriel 1892 "Analyses: A. Espinas. Histoire des doctrines économiques. Paris, Colin, 1892," RPFE 34: 69-75.
  41. Tarde, Gabriel 1892 "Une nouvelle école italienne «le positivisme critique» ," AAC 7: 208-211.
  42. Tarde, Gabriel 1892 "Le crime des foules," AAC 7: 353-386.
  43. Tarde, Gabriel 1892 "Bibilographie: Bribes de statistiques Américaines," AAC 7: 691-698.
  44. Tarde, Gabriel 1892 Les Geants chauves, Revue bleue.
  45. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Réponse à M.R.Berthelot," Revue de Metaphysique et de Molale.
  46. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Les monades et la science sociale," Revue International de Sociologie.
  47. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Revue général: Questions sociales," RPFE 35: 618-638.
  48. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "La logique sociale des sentiments," RPFE 36: 561-594.
  49. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Note et discussions: Les transformations du droit," RPFE 36: 623-629.
  50. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Biologie et sociologie: Réponse au Dr Bianchi ," AAC 8: 7-20.
  51. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Pro domo mea: Réponse à M. Ferri," AAC 8: 258-276.
  52. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "Revue bibliographique: Les Vaudois, par A. Berard, conseiller général de l'ain, substitut du procureur général de Grenoble," AAC 8: 334-338.
  53. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 "La sociologie criminelle et le droit pénal," AAC 8: 513-525.
  54. Tarde, Gabriel 1893 Foules et sectes au point de vue criminel, Revue des Duex Mondes.
  55. Tarde, Gabriel 1894 La serie histoirique des etats logiques, Revue International de Sociologie.
  56. Tarde, Gabriel 1894 La sociologie elementaire, Annales de l'institut International de Sociologie.
  57. Tarde, Gabriel 1894 "Revue bibliographique: Les malfaiteurs de profession, par Louis Puibaraud, ancien chef du cabinet du préfet de police (Flammarion, éditeur, 1893).," AAC 9: 108-111.
  58. Tarde, Gabriel 1894 "Les crimes de haine," AAC 9: 242-254.
  59. Tarde, Gabriel 1894 "Les délits impoursuivis," AAC 9: 641-650.
  60. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Criminalité et santé sociale," RPFE 39: 148-162.
  61. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Le transformisme social," RPFE 40: 26-40.
  62. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Revue bibliographique: Saint François d'Assise, étude sociale et médicale par le Dr Bournet (1 vol. in-8, orné d'un portrait et de nembreuses reproductions d'anciennes gravures, Lyon, Storck, 1893," AAC 10: 138-142.
  63. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Revue critique: Congrès de sociologie," AAC 10: 206-207.
  64. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Revue critique: L'instinct de domination: À Jacques Dumas," AAC 10: 207-211.
  65. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "Revue critique: La diminution du crime en Angleterre," AAC 10: 211-214.
  66. Tarde, Gabriel 1895 "La sociologie élémentaire," AIIS 1: 209-243.
  67. Tarde, Gabriel 1896 "L'idée de l'«organisme social»," RPFE 41: 637-646.
  68. Tarde, Gabriel 1896 "Nouvelles: À Monsieur le Directeur de la Scuola Positiva," AAC 11: 131-132.[서명란에 Lyon, le 18 novembre 1895로 됨]
  69. Tarde, Gabriel 1896 "L'idée de l'«organisme social»," AAC 11: 418-428. [Tarde, RPFE 41:637-646의 재게재]
  70. Tarde, Gabriel 1896 "Bibliographie: Organisme et Société, thèse de doctorat présenté à la Faculté des lettres de Paris, par René Worms, auditeur au Conseil d'Etat, Directeur de la Revue internationale de sociologie (Paris, Giard et Brière, 1893).," AAC 11: 452. [G. T.의 서명]
  71. Tarde, Gabriel 1896 "La criminalité professionelle," AAC 11: 538-560. [ Rapport au quatriàme congràs international d'anthropologie criminelle]
  72. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 "L'idée d'opposition," RPFE 43: 1-18, 160-175.
  73. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 "La graphologie," RPFE 44: 337-363.
  74. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 Sympathie Synthese, Revue Francaise d'Edimbourg.
  75. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 "Note sur les rapports de la biologie et de la sociologie," AIIS 3: 189-198.
  76. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 "Souvenir de transports judiciaires: à M. Labori, avocat près la Cour d'appel," AAC 12: 293-300.
  77. Tarde, Gabriel 1897 "Notes et documents de psychologie normale et pathologique: La jeunesse criminelle: Lettre à M. Buisson, ancien directeur général de l'enseignement primaire, professeur à la Sorbonne," AAC 12: 452-472.
  78. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 Le public et la foule, Revue de Paris.
  79. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "Qu'est-ce que la crime? ," RPFE 46: 337-355.
  80. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "Problèmes de criminalité," AAC 13: 369-.409.
  81. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "Revue des journaux et sociétés savantes: Suggestion et science sociale," AAC 13: 495. [G. T.의 서명]
  82. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "Bibliographie: Sensations d'Orient, par Émile Laurent, Paris 1896.," AAC 13: 579. [G. T.의 서명]
  83. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "Les transformations de l'impunité," AAC 13: 615-631.
  84. Tarde, Gabriel 1898 "La théorie organique des sociétés ," AIIS 4: 237-260.
  85. Tarde, Gabriel 1899 "L'opinion et la conversation," Revue de Paris.
  86. Tarde, Gabriel 1899 "Revue critique: L'ame du criminel, par le Dr Maurice de Fleury (Félix Alcan, éditeur, 1898) ," AAC 14: 297-304.
  87. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 "Correspondance: Réponse à M. Espinas" RPFE 51: 661-664.
  88. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 "La realité sociale," RPFE 52: 457-477.
  89. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 L'action intermentale, AAC.
  90. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 La criminalite et les phenomenes economiques, AAC.
  91. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 La psychologie intermentale, Revue International de Sociologie.
  92. Tarde, Gabriel 1901 "L'action des faits futurs," Revue de Metaphysique et de Molale.
  93. Tarde, Gabriel 1902 "L'invention consideree comme moteur de l'evolution sociale," Revue International de Sociologie.
  94. Tarde, Gabriel 1902 "Quelques mots sur le matélialisme historique," AIIS 8: 283-289.
  95. Tarde, Gabriel 1903 L'interpsycologie, Bulletin de l'institut General Psycologique.
  96. Tarde, Gabriel 1903 Les classes sociales, Revue International de Sociologie.
  97. Tarde, Gabriel 1903 "Augstin Cournot," AIIS 9: 87-104.
  98. Tarde, Gabriel 1904 "La psycologie et la sociologie," AIIS 10: 67-81.
  99. Tarde, Gabriel 1904 "Notice sur la vie et l'oeure de Charles Leveque," Seances et Travaux de l'Academie des Sciences Morales et Politiques.
  100. Tarde, Gabriel 1904 "Lettre autobiographique," Revue Universelle.
  101. Tarde, Gabriel 1904 "La sociologie et les sciences sociales," Revue International de Sociologie.

타르드 관련 문헌

  1. Acuna, Alvaro Santana 2008 "At the Edge of Classicism: The Boundaries of the Sociological Canon and the Rise of Social (Adam Smith's Sentiments and Gabriel Tarde's Monads),"
  2. Anonymous 1904 "Nécrologie: Gabriel Tarde," RPFE 57: 685.
  3. Anonymous 2004 Gabriel Tarde A B C, Agen: ÉNAP.
  4. Alliez, Élic 1999a "Présentation: Tarde et le problème de la constitiuton," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Monadologie et sociologie, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-1, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 9-32.
  5. ________ 1999b "Notice bio-bibliographique," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Les lois sociales, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-4, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 139-151.
  6. ________ 2000 "Avetissement," in Tarde Gabriel 2000 « Maine de Biran et l'évolutionisme en psychologie », Paris: Institut Sanofi-Synthèlabo: 9-11.
  7. ________ 2001 "Différence et répétiton de Gabriel Tarde," Multitudes 7: 171-175.
  8. Alliez, Éric 2003 "Remarks on Whitehead,"
    (http://www.goldsmiths.ac.uk/csisp/papers/Alliez_Remarks_on_Whitehead.pdf)
  9. Antoine, Jean-Philippe 2001b "Statistique et métaphore: note sur la méthode sociologique de Tarde," in Tarde, Gabriel 2001a Les lois de l'imitation, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-1, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond: 7-42.
  10. ________ 2001b "Tarde, commun sensationnel," Multitudes 7: 203-211. Arnoldi, Jacob & Borch, Christian 2007 "Market Crowds between Imitation and Control," Theory, Culture & Society 24: 164-180.
  11. Arnoldi, Jakob & Borch, Christian 2007 "Market Crowds between Imitation and Control," Theory, Culture & Society 24(7-8): 164-180.
  12. Arréat, L. 1905 "Analyses: G. Tarde. Fragment d'histoire future. Storck, Lyon, 1904.," RPFE 60: 88-89.
  13. Barry, Andrew & Thrift, Nigel 20071016 "Gabriel Tarde: imitation, invention and economy," Economy and Society 36(4): 509-525.
  14. Beirne, Piers 1987 "Between classicism and positivism: Crime and penality in the writngs of Gabriel Tarde," Criminology 25(4): 785-819.
  15. Béjin, André 2008 "Préface: La Sexualité et l'amour selon Tarde," in Tarde, Gabriel 2008 La Morale sexuelle, Paris: Éditions Payot & Rivages.
  16. Belot, 1896 "La logique sociale d'apres M. Tarde," RPFE.
  17. Bergson, Henri 1909 "Préface," in Tarde, Alfred & Tarde, Guillaume 1909 Gabriel Tarde, Paris: Louis-Michud: 5-6.
  18. Bertrand, Alexis 1891 "Revue bibliographique: G. Tarde. Les lois de l'imitation. Étude sociologique, Paris, Alcan (VIII-431 pages).," AAC 6: 315-321.
  19. ________ 1904 "Un essai de cosmologie sociale: les theses monadologiques de Gabriel Tarde," AAC.
  20. Besnard, Philippe 1995 "Durkheim critique de Tarde : des Régles au suiside," in Borlandi, Massimo & Mucchielli, Laurent [éd] 1995 La sociologie et sa méthode : Les Régles de Durkheim un siècle après, Paris: L'Harmmatan.
  21. ________ 2003 "Durkheim critique de Tarde, " Études durkheimiennes, Genève: DROZ: 65-86.
  22. Borlandi, Massimo & Mucchielli, Laurent [éds] 1995 La sociologie et sa méthode : Les Régles de Durkheim un siècle après, Paris: L'Harmmatan.
  23. Borch, Christian 20071016 "Crowds and economic life: bringing an old figure back in," Economy and Society 36(4): 549-573.
  24. Borch, Christian 2008 "Foam architecture: Managing co-isolated associations," Economy and Society 37(4): 548-571.
  25. Borlandi, Massimo 2000 "Tarde et les criminologues italiens de son temps," Revue d'histoire des Sciences Humaines 3: 7-56.
  26. Bouglé, Célestin 1905 Un sociologue individualiste, Revue de Paris.
  27. Bournet, A. 1894 "Nouvelles: M. G. Tarde a perdu sa grand' mère...," AAC 9: 640.
  28. Clark, Terry N.1969 Gabriel Tarde on Communication & Social Influence, University of Chicago.
  29. ________ 1973 Prophets and Patrons : The french university and the emergence of the social sciences, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  30. Comijn, Hans 2005 "a tardean sociology of mathematics,"
  31. Corre, A. 1891 "Bibliographie: La philosophie pénale, par. G. Tarde, un volume in-8 de 566 pages, Bibliothèque de criminologie, Storck et Masson, éditeurs, Lyon-Paris.," AAC 6: 93-103.
  32. Dagau (Henri), 1904 Les sociologiques contemporaias : M. Gabriel Tarde, La Grande Revue.
  33. Dauriac, Lionel 1898 "Analyses: G. Tarde. L'opposition universelle. Essai d'une théorie des contraires. Paris, F. Alcan, 1897. 1 vol. in-8 (445p.) de la Bibliothèque de philosophique contemporaine.," RPFE 45: 81-89.
  34. Davis, Michael Marks, Jr. 1906 Gabriel Tarde: An Essay In Sociological Theory, New York.
  35. ________ 1905 La philosophie de Tarde, Annee philosophieque.
  36. Devarieux, Anne 2000 "Gabriel Tarde lecteur de Maine de Biran, ou «la difficulé formidable»," in Tarde Gabriel 2000 « Maine de Biran et l'évolutionisme en psychologie », Paris: Institut Sanofi-Synthèlabo: 13-49.
  37. Duncan, David C 2002 "Gabriel Tarde - The first economic Psychologist? : A review of Psychologie Economique by Gabriel Tarde (1902). F. Alcan, Paris," Journal of Economic Psychology 23: 149-156.
  38. Durkheim, Émile 1893 De la division du travail social, Alcan
  39. ________ [1895] 1960 Les régles de la méthode sociologique, Paris: PUF
  40. ________ 1895 "Crime et santé sociale," RPFE 39: 518-523.
  41. ________ [1897] 1967 Le Suicide: Étude sociologique, Paris: P.U.F.
  42. Eichthal, Eugène D' 1902 "Revue critique: La psyhcologie économique," RPFE 53: 523-532.
  43. Espinas, Alfred 1901 "Étre ou ne pas étre : Du postulat de la sociologie," RPFH 51(5): 449-480.
  44. Favre, Pierre 1983 "Gabriel Tarde et la mauvaise fortune d'un " baptême sociologique " de la science politique," Revue française de sociologie 24(1): 3-30.
  45. Fuller, Steve 20041101 "Intellectuals: An endangered species in the twenty-first century?," Economy and Society 33(4): 463-483.
  46. Gane, Mike 20050501 "Durkheim's scenography of suicide," Economy and Society 34(2): 223-240.
  47. Goblot, Edmond 1898 "Analyses: G. Tarde. Les lois sociales, Esquisse d'une sociologie. Alcan, 1898, 1 vol. in-8 de la Bibl. de phil. cont., 169p.," RPFE 46: 206-209.
  48. Joseph, Isaac 1999 "Gabriel Tarde: le monde comme féerie," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Les lois sociales, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-4, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 9-36.
  49. ________ 2001 Tarde avec Park: À quoi servent les foules?," Multitudes 7: 212-219.
  50. Katz, Elihu 1992 "L'Héritage de Gabriel Tarde: Un paradigme pour la recherche sur l'opinion et la communication," Hermès 11-12: 265-274.
  51. ________ 1999 "Theorizing diffusion: Tarde and sorokin revisited," Annals of the Academy of Political & Social Science.
  52. Kinnunen Jussi, 1996, Gabriel Tarde as a Founding Father of Innovation Diffusion, Acta sociologica.
  53. Latour, Bruno 2001 "Gabriel Tarde and the End of the Social," in Patrick Joyce ed. 2001 The Social in Question, New Bearings in History and the Social Sciences, London: Routledge: 117-132 (http://www.bruno-latour.fr/articles/article/082.html) .
  54. ________ 2004 "Never too late to read Tarde," Domus.
    (http://www.bruno-latour.fr/presse/presse_art/GB-DOMUS%2010-04.html)
  55. ________ 2005 Re-assembling The Social. An Introduction To Actor-Network Theory, Oxford University Press (=2006 tr. Nicolas Guilhot et revise Latour, Bruno Changer de société: Refaire de la sociologie, Paris: La Découverte).
  56. Latour, Bruno & Lépinay, Vincent-Antonin 2008 L'économie science des intérêts passionnés: Introduction à l'anthropologie économique de Gabriel Tarde, Paris: La Decouverté.
  57. Lazzarato, Maurizio 1999 "Gabriel Tarde: Un vitalisme politique," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 Monadologie et sociologie, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-1, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 103-150.
  58. ________ 2001 "La psychologie économique contre l'économique politique," Multitudes 7: 193-202. (http://multitudes.samizdat.net/La-Psychologie-economique-contre-l.html)
  59. ________ 2002 Puissance de l'invention: La psychologie économique de Gabriel Tarde contre l'économie politique, Paris: Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  60. ________ 2004 "Créer des mondes: Capitalisme contemporain et guerres «esthétiques»", Multitudes 15.(http://multitudes.samizdat.net/Creer-des-mondes-Capitalisme.html)
  61. ________ 2004 Les révolutions du capitalisme, Paris: Les empêcheurs de penser en rond.
  62. Lepinary, Vincent-Antonin 20071101 "Economy of the germ: capital, accumulation and vibration," Economy and Society 36(4): 526-548.
  63. Lester Ward., 1900, Tarde's Social Lows, Scienc.
  64. Letonturier. E., 2000, Gabriel Tarde lacommunication et des reseaux, Cahiers Internaitonaoux de Sociologie.
  65. Lévy-Bruhl, L. 1890 "Analyses: G. Tarde. La philosophie pénale. 1 vol. de la Bibliothèque de criminologie, gr. in-8, 566 pages,1890, chez Storck à Lyon, chez Masson à Paris.," RPFE 30: 654-669.
  66. Lubek, Ian 1981 "Histoire de psychologies sociales perdues: le cas de Gabriel Tarde," Revue française de sociologie 22(3): 361-395.
  67. Malaim, E. 1903, L'economie politique de M. Tarde, Revue d'éconnomie politique.
  68. Marsden, Paul 2000, Forefathers of Memetics : Gabriel Tarde and the Laws of Imitation, Jounal of Memetics - Evolutionary models of Information Transmission 4
  69. Martin, Jean-Clet 1999 "Tarde aujourd'hui," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 L'oppositon universelle, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-3, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 13-44.
  70. ________ 2001 "Tarde: une nouvelle monadologie," Multitudes 7: 186-192.
  71. Martin, Robert Vance. 1939 A comparative study of gabriel Tarde's and William McDugall's theories of imitation, Duke University.
  72. Martin, Thierry 2002 "Tarde, lecteur de Cournot," in Tarde, Gabriel 200210 Philosophie de l'histoire et sciance sociale: La philosphie de Cournot, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-4, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond: 9-26.
  73. Millet, J. 1970 Gabriel Tarde et la philosophie de l'histoire, Vrin.
  74. Moscovici, sergh 1981 L’Age des foules: un traite' historique de psychologie des masses,Paris: Fayard.
  75. Mucchielli, Laurent 1998 La découverte du social: naissance de la sociologie en france, Paris: La Découverte.
  76. ________ 2000a "Introduction," Revue d'histoire des sciences humaines, 3: 3-5.
  77. ________ 2000b "Criminologie, hygiénisme et eugénisme en France(1870-1914) ," Revue d'histoire des sciences humaines, 3: 57-88.
  78. ________ 2000c "Tardomania? Réflexions sur les usages contemporaines de Tarde", Revue d'histoire des sciences humaines 3: 161-184.
  79. ________ 2004 Mythes et histoire des sciences humaines, Paris: La Découverte.
  80. Nigel, Thrift 20060501 "Re-inventing invention: new tendencies in capitalist commodification," Economy and Society 35(2): 279-306.
  81. Palante, G. 1898 "Analyses: G. Tarde. Fragment d'histoire future. Opuscule de 52 pages. Paris, V. Giard et Brière, éditeurs, 1896.," RPFE 46: 328-329.
  82. Palmas, Karl 2008 "Follow the phlegm: Tracing the infinitesimal in male networks of power,"
  83. Paulhan, Frédéric 1890 "Analyses: Tarde. Les lois de l'imitation, Étude sociologique. 1 vol. in-8, 431p. Paris, Alcan, 1890," RPFE 30: 170-182.
  84. ________ 1892 "Analyses: Études sociales et pénales. 1 vol. in-8 (460p.) de la Bibliothèque de criminologie. Lyon, A. Strock; Paris, G. Masson, 1892.," RPFE 34: 75-80.
  85. ________ 1899 "Analyses: G. Tarde. édtudes de psyhcologie sociale. 1 vol. in-8 de 326p. Paris, Girard et Brière, 1898," RPFE 47: 335-339.
  86. ________ 1902 "Analyses: G. Tarde. L'opinion et la foule. 1 vol. in-8 de la Bibliothèque de philosophie contemporaine, 226p., Paris, Alcan, 1901.," RPFE 53: 201-207.
  87. Renneville, Marc 2004a "Le printemps des sciences du crime," in Tarde, Gabriel 200409 La criminalité comparée, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-5, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond: 7-23.
  88. ________ 2004b "Gabriel Tarde, l'hyrondel de la criminologie," in Tarde, Gabriel 200409 La criminalité comparée, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-5, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond: 207-217.
  89. Richard, Gaston 1902 "Analyses: Psyhcologie économique, 2 vol. in-8 de la Bibliothèque de philosophie contemporaine, Paris, Félix Alcan, 1902.," RPFE 54: 640-648.
  90. Schérer, René 1999 "Homo ludens: des stratégies vitales," in Tarde, Gabriel 1999 La logique sociale, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde I-2, Paris: Institut Synthélabo: 15-56.
  91. ________ 2001 "Tarde, puissance de l'invention," Multitudes 7: 177-185.
  92. Shone, Steve J. 1992 The irrelevance of rationality: Gabriel Tarde and Rastafarisme (Tarde, Gabriel Jamaica),PhD Thesis, University of California, Riverside, pp. 243.
  93. Tarde, Guillaume & Tarde, Alfred 1909 Gabriel Tarde: Introduction et pages choisies par ses fils, Louis - Michaud.
  94. Taymans, S. J., A. C., 1950 "Tarde and Schumpeter: A similar vision," Quarterly Journal of Economics 64(4): 611-622.
  95. Toscano, Alberto 2007 "Powers of pacification: state and empire in Gabriel Tarde," Economy and Society 36(4): 597-613.
  96. Tosti, G. 1897 The sociological theories of Gabriel Tarde, Polit. Sci. quarterly.
  97. Vaschide, N. 1904 La psychologie de M. Tarde, AAC.
  98. Vatin, François 2000 "Cournot, Tarde et la fin des temps," L'homme et la Société 136-137: 127-156.
  99. Vargas, Eduardo Viana 1992 Gabriel Tarde e a rrcicrossociologia, Dissertação de mestrado em Antropologia Social, PPGAS, Museu Nacional, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro.
  100. ________ 발표 연도 불명확 "A microssociologia de Gabriel Tarde," (http://www.anpocs.org.br/portal/publicacoes/rbcs_00_27/rbcs27_06.htm)
  101. ________ 2000 Antes Tarde do que nunca: Gabriel Tarde e a emergência das ciências sociais, Rio de Janeiro: Contra Capa Livraria.
  102. ________ 2004 "Multiplicando os agentes do mundo: Gabriel Tarde e a sociologia infinitesimal," Revista brasileira de ciências sociais 19(55): 172-176. (http://redalyc.uaemex.mx/redalyc/pdf/107/10705512.pdf: PDF)
  103. Vierkandt A. 1899 Gabriel Tarde und die Bestrebungen der sociologie, Zeitschrift fur social-wissenschaft.
  104. Williams, Rosalind H. 1982 Dream Worlds: mass Consumption in late Nineteenth-Century France, The Regents of the University of California
  105. Worms, René 1904 Gabriel Tarde, Revue International de Sociologie.
  106. ________ 1905 "La philosophie sociale de G. Tarde," RPFE 60: 121-156.
  107. Wroblewska, 1896, Die zegenwartige sociologische Bewegung in Frankreich mit besonderer Rucksicht aul Gabriel Tarde, Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie.
  108. Zourabichvili, François 2003 "Le pouvoir en devenir: Tarde et l'actualité," in Tarde, Gabriel [1898] 200310 Les transformations du pouvoir, Œuvres de Gabriel Tarde II-2, Les empêcheurs de penser en rond: 7-37.

기타 문헌

저서 인용 약호

  • AAC:[1886-1893] Archives de l'anthropologie criminelle et des sciences pénales [1893-] Archives d'anthropologie criminelle de criminologie et de psychologie normale et pathologique
  • AIIS: Annales de l'institut international de sociologie, Paris: V.Giard & E. Brière.
  • RIS: Revue internationale de sociologie
  • RPFE: Revue philosophique de la France et de l'étranger
Posted by 상겔스 상겔스
1843 : 3월 10일. 장-가브리엘 타르드(Jean-Gabriel Tarde), 도르도뉴 사를라(Dordogne, Sarlat)에서 태어나다.
1850 : 가브리엘의 아버지 피에르-폴 타르드 사망(타르드 7살)
1862 : 타르드, 눈병에 걸리다.(19살) 25살까지 계속됨.
1869 : 사를라의 재판보조(juge suppléant)에 임관. (26살)
1873 : 샤트렝트 뤼펙(Chatrente, Ruffec)의 검사보(substitut de Procureur de la Republique)에 임관(30살)
1875 : 예심판사(Juge d'Instruction)로서 다시 사를라로 돌아감(32세)
1876 : 테오뒤르 리보(Théodule Ribot)를 중심으로 『철학평론』 (Revue philosophique de la france et de l'étranger) 창간
1877 : 마르트 바르디-드리슬(Marthe Bardy-Delisle)과 결혼(34세)
1880 : 8월 -- 타르드, 「신념과 욕망 ―― 그 측정가능성」(La croyance et le désir : la possibilité de leur mesure)이 『철학평론』(Revue philosophique de la française et de l'étrangers, 1876년 창간)에 게재. 이것이 타르드의 최초의 간행된 논문이 된다.(37세)
1886 : 타르드, 『비교범죄학』(La Criminalité comparée) 출판 (43세)
         리용대학교 의학부 법의학 교수 알렉상드르 라카사뉴(Alexsandre Lacassagne), 리용대학교 법학부 형법학교수 가로(R. Garraud), 리용대학교 의학부 법의학 감독관(chef de travaux) 앙리 코타뉴(Henri Coutagne)를 중심으로 『범죄인류학잡지』(Archives de l'Anthropologie Criminelle et des sciences pénales) 창간
1890 : 타르드, 『형사철학』(Philosophie pénale) 출판 (47세)
         타르드, 『모방의 법칙 ―― 사회학 연구』 (Les lois de l'imitation: Étude sociologique) 출판 (47세) 
1891 : (La Roque Gajac)에서 모친 사망(48세)
1892 : 타르드, 『형사적, 사회적 연구』 (Études pénales et sociales) 출판 (49세)
1893 : 타르드, 『법의 변천 ―― 사회학 연구』 (Les transformation du droit) 출판 (50세) 
         1월 -- 르네 웜스(René Worms)를 중심으로 「국제사회학협회」(Institut international de sociologie)가 창설되고, 그 기관지인 『국제사회학잡지』(Revue internationale de sociologie)가 창간됨. 타르드도 가입하여 「모나드와 사회과학」(Les monades et sciences sociales)을 기고. (50세) 
         라카사뉴와 함께 『범죄인류학잡지』(Archives d'anthropologie criminelle de criminologie et de psychologie normale et pathologique로 잡지명 개정)의 공동편집자가 됨(50세)
1894 : 타르드, 법무부 범죄통계국장(directeur de la Statistique Judiciaire au Ministère du la Justice)이 되어 파리로 이주(51세)
        5월 ~ 8월 : 뒤르켐, 「사회학적 방법의 규준」을 『철학평론』에 4회로 나누어 게재
        10월 1일 ~ 4일 : 제1회 국제사회학협회 학회대회가 개최됨. 여기에서 타르드는 「사회학의 두 요소」 (les deux élément de sociologie) 발표 (51세)
1895 : 타르드, 『사회논리학』 (La logique sociale) 출판 (52세)
         타르드,『모방의 법칙』 제2판 출판 
         타르드, 『사회학시론・잡문집』 (Essais et mélanges sociologiques) 출판 
         르네 웜스를 중심으로 「파리사회학회」 (Société de sociologie de Paris) 창설됨. 타르드는 초기 파리사회학회장을 역임
        『국제사회학협회연보』 (Annales de l'institut international de sociologie) 창간
         9월 30일 ~ 10월 3일 : 파리에서 제2회 국제사회학회 학예회 대회 개최
1896 : 타르드,「미래사의 단편」 (Fragment de l'histoire future)을『국제사회학협회연보』에 기고 (53세)
1897 : 타르드, 『보편적 대립』 (L'opposition universelle) 출판 (54세)
         타르드, 「사회과학 자유학원」 (Collège Libre des Sciences Sociales)에 가서 『사회법칙』의 원형이 된 3회의 강연을 함
1898 : 타르드, 『사회법칙』(Les lois sociales) 출판 (55세)
         타르드, 「사회과학 자유학원」에 가서 「권력의 변천」의 원형이 된 강연을 함.
1899 : 타르드, 『권력의 변천』 (Les transformation du pouvoir) 출판 (56세) 
         타르드, 『사회심리학연구』 (Études psychologique sociale) 출판
1900 : 타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 근대철학의 자리를 차지. (57세)
         타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 「간정신 심리학」(Psychologie Intermentale) 강의를 함.
         타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 1900년~1901년에 걸쳐 「경제심리학」 (La Psychologie Économique) 강의를 함.
1901 : 타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 1901~1902년에 걸쳐 「도덕의 변천」 (Les transformation du moral) 강의를 함. (58세)
         타르드, 『여론과 군중』(L'opinion et la foule) 출판
1902 : 타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 1902‐1903년에 걸쳐 「형사철학」 (La Philosophie pénale :목요강의)와 「쿠르노 철학의 관념들」 (Les idées philosophiques de Cournot :토요강의)의 강의를 함. (59세)
         타르드, 『경제심리학』 (Psychologie Économique) 출판
1903 : 타르드, 콜레쥬 드 프랑스에서 1903~1904년에 걸쳐 「간정신 심리학의 요소들」 (Les Éléments de la Psychologie Intermentale) 강의를 함.(60세)
1904 : 5월 12일, 타르드, 파리에서 사망(61세)
1909 : 9월 12일, 사랄라의 재판소 정면에 가브리엘 타르드의 동상이 설치됨.
Posted by 상겔스 상겔스
<읽기>라기보다는 이것저것 조사하기가 적합할 것이다. 마우리찌오 라짜라또의 책 두권을 입수했는데, 그 중 하나가 타르드를 다루고 있다. 들뢰즈도 타르드에 대해 꽤 여러번 언급하고 있다. 문제는 내가 타르드의 책을 한 번도 읽어본 적이 없다는 사실. 그런데 우리나라에 타르드의 책이 번역된 적이 있었나? (잠시 검색을 위해 이 페이지에서 벗어나 보기. 결과, 없다....) 그러므로 여기에 쓰는 것은 기본적인 조사와 자료 수집이다. 더 나은 자료가 있으면 계속 소개할 요량.

<모방>이 복제와 약간의 창조를 모두 포함하는 것이라면 세상은 <모방>으로 가득 차 있다. 우선 인간과 식물, 동물 등의 생물은 부계와 모계의 유전자를 복제하여 탄생한다. 몸의 세포는 수정란이 세포분열하여, 즉 복제하여 만들어진다. 자연계의 물질을 보더라도 동일한 원자나 분자가 대거 존재한다. 원자나 분자의 복제에 의해 물질이 성립된다고 볼 수 있으리라. 공장은 어떠한가? 공장 역시 상품이 대량 생산되는 곳이다. 공장의 기계가 동일한 물건을 대량으로 복제하고 있다고 볼 수 있으리라. 정보의 경우도 신문, 잡지 등은 인쇄기를 통해 복제, 인쇄되어 배포된다. 텔레비전, 라디오 등은 방송국이 송신하고 텔레비전 수상기나 라디오 수신기가 수신하는 것이다. 정보 역시 이런 식으로 복제되고 있다. CD나 DVD, 비디오 역시 대량으로 복제되어 판매되고 있다. 사진 역시 경치나 인물을 찍은 것, 즉 복제이다. 인터넷의 메일 송수신이나 홈페이지, 블로그의 열람 역시 복제이다. 회화, 강연, 강의 등의 정보 전달 역시 송신자에게서 수신자에게로 정보의 복제일 뿐만 아니라 독서도 마찬가지로 책에서 두뇌로의 정보의 복제이다. 눈으로 본 풍경은 머릿속에 기억으로서 복제된다. 그리하여 우리의 두뇌는 복제된 정보가 가득 차 있다. 신제품의 개발 역시 개발자의 두뇌 안에 있는 제품 이미지를 설계서에 써서, 즉 복제하여 제조 기계를 이용해 제품이라는 형태로 복제한 것이라고 볼 수 있다.
그렇다면, 이제 문제이다. 창조, 또는 발명이란 무엇인가? 그것은 복제한 것이기는 하되 '새로운 조합'을 한 것이다. 가령 사람들의 복장은 모두 차이가 난다고 생각되지만, 잘 보면 복제 제품의 편성, 또는 배치, 또는 성좌의 차이에 불과하다. 그렇다면 새로운 조합 또는 배치의 탄생 메커니즘, 복제 기능의 메커니즘, 그것을 통제하는 것은 무엇인가? 자연계에서의 모방은 자연의 법칙을 따른다. 자연의 법칙은 불변적이면서 보편적이다. 한편, 사회에서의 모방은 법률이나 규칙, 관습 등에 따르게끔 통제된다. 모방에 의해 가능한 것은 편성, 짜임, 배치의 차이에 따라 여러 가지 형태를 띤다. 인간이 만든 법률, 상품, 조직 등도 모방이 있기 때문에 다양하게 변화한다. 인간은 법칙이나 규칙에 따라 모방하며, 여러 가지 물건이나 생각, 행동을 낳는다. 무의식적, 의식적으로 법칙을 인식하여 활용하는 능력을 갖고 있음을 나타내는 것이다. 예를 들어 아이에게 문법을 가르치지 않아도 문법에 따라서 말을 하게 된다. 아이는 문법 그 자체를 직접 보거나 묻지 않기 때문에 문법의 존재를 의식하지 않고 있다. 문법을 의식하면 매끄러운 대화를 할 수 없다. 이로부터도 인간은 자연법칙이나 규칙 등을 무의식적으로 인식하며 무의식 속에서 활용하는 능력을 갖고 있음을 알 수 있다.
복제를 하기 위해서는 복제의 원본이 필요한데, 그 최초의 기원은 무엇일까? 그것은 모방에 의한 것이 아닐 것이므로 변함이 없을 것이기 때문에 자연법칙이라는 것을 알 수 있다.
목적이나 수단도 모방된다. 생물의 수정란에서 개체가 발생하는 것에 대해 생각해 보자. 개체 발생은 세포 분열에 의해 게놈의 복제를 반복하면서 진행된다. 이 과정은 자기 조직성에 의한 것이라고 말해진다. 세포분열과 분화는 목적의 복제와 목적을 달성하기 위한 수단의 분화이다. 수단으로서의 기능은 게놈의 정보에 토대를 두고, 외부로부터 물질, 에너지, 정보를 받아들여 내부로 편입함으로써, 즉 모방함으로써 형성된다. 이 과정에서 중요한 것은 목적을 복제하고 있다는 것이다. 목적을 공유함으로써 개체로서 통일과 조화를 취할 수 있는 계층구조가 형성된다. 또한 외부로부터 물질, 에너지, 정보를 입수하여 모방함으로써 외부 환경에 대한 적응을 가능케 하는 것이다.
기업에서도 창업자가 사장을 하고 기업규모가 작을 때에는 목적이 쉽게 공유된다. 사장의 교체, 급속한 성장, 합병 등에 의해 내부에 분파주의나 충돌이 생겨나 목적의 공유가 무너지면 경영을 잘 되지 않게 된다.
어떤 학설의 부정 역시 모방이다. 부정과 긍정의 차이는 <~이다>와 <~ 아니다>의 차이로, 그저 한 개 반의 문자만 다를 뿐이다. 자연과학에서의 플러스와 마이너스의 관계도 마찬가지로 모방관계로 볼 수 있다. 선과 악, 높음과 낮음, 강함과 약함 등과 같은 반대 관계 역시 모방의 관계에 있다고 말할 수 있다.
모든 것은 모방이고, 다른 것은 배치일 뿐. 이런 견해, 어디서 많이 들어보지 못했던가?
Posted by 상겔스 상겔스


티스토리 툴바